For those following, our blog has now moved to DrJohnGKuna.com. Thanks, and see you over there!
John G. Kuna, PsyD and Associates Counseling
Review of current research related to the professional practice of psychology.
Thursday, July 3, 2014
Monday, June 16, 2014
Motivational urges, Motor System, and Neurological Correlates
How can we measure the connection
between human urges, the translation of those urges in the form of behavior,
and the neurological mechanism of action? This is precisely the question Gupta
and Aron set out to answer in their article, “Urges for food and money spill
over into motor system excitability before action is taken.” No doubt, much of
human behavior is driven by urges. In psychological jargon, the operational
definition of an urge can be defined as how much someone desires an object,
relative to its perceived value.
Wondering whether the urges for food and
money are detectable by way of motor system excitability, the researchers in
this article employed the use of transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) and
concurrent electromyography to test their hypothesis. They hypothesized that
stimuli associated with stronger urges, in this case food and money, would
correspond to higher motor excitability and that this excitability would be
evident before the participant consciously decided which motor response to
make.
As is typical, the experiment
consisted of 17 young adults (9 male, mean age=21.9) who were instructed not to
eat for 4 hours prior to the study. They were presented with 60 food items
ranging from candy bars to clam juice, and were told to rate them on a 5 point
likert scale. Two other similar experiments were conducted using a monetary
paradigm instead of food. For all three experiments, there was a randomized
presentation of food items (the stimuli), and each trial began by simple
priming: either a picture of food or an empty rectangle. A choice screen
followed, providing the participants with a Yes/No option corresponding to
either the left or right index finger. Further, this Yes/No option was
randomized—that is, participants would not always be presented with the “yes”
option corresponding to the right index finger.
This
is interesting since it negates the possibility simple response preparation.
Nor can this be simply a matter of increased arousal, since the effect was
present only when action was required. Concerning this, the researchers note
that “it must also reflect motivational processing that is upstream from the
corticospinal system…[that] likely involves brain systems such as the orbital
frontal cortex and associated limbic circuitry, including the ventral striatum ⁄ nucleus-accumbens and ventral pallidum.”
(Gupta, 2010, p. 186).
The article mentions its
contribution to the growing literature of embodied cognition. Indeed, with the
sensitive testing method they used, they provide the ability of observing the
so called motivational “spill-over” into the motor system, even before the
motor system knows exactly what to do.
Further research is needed to
investigate the action the researchers anticipated, namely that the
motivational spill-over will correspond to heightened activation of motor
regions of the basal ganglia.
by Phillip J. Kuna
for John G. Kuna, PsyD and Associates
Licensed Psychologist
References
Gupta, N., &
Aron, A. R. (2011). Urges for food and money spill over into motor system
excitability
before action is taken. European Journal Of Neuroscience, 33(1),
183-188. doi:10.1111/j.1460-9568.2010.07510.x
Monday, June 9, 2014
Schizophrenia and Adolescent Substance Abuse
The classic Carlson
text on the physiology of behavior does an excellent job providing a review
of the literature concerning the pharmacology, neurology and epidemiology of
schizophrenia. I was a bit disappointed, however, with a distinct lack of treatment
concerning the (possible) relationship between schizophrenia and substance
abuse. More specifically, I was interested in any correlations between
schizophrenia and adolescent
substance abuse. Carlson makes the following observation, but leaves the reader
hanging: “MRI studies suggest that schizophrenia is not caused by a
degenerative process as are Parkinson’s disease…Instead, a sudden rapid loss of
brain volume typically occurs during young adulthood… [This process] begins
prenatally and then lies dormant until puberty, when some unknown mechanism
triggers degeneration of some neurons (p. 565).”
What, then, is the role of substance
abuse of adolescents who later exhibit symptoms of schizophrenia? Fortuitously,
research revealed a 2005 article: “Adolescence,
schizophrenia and drug abuse: a window of vulnerability.” As a review of the
literature, this article also provided a copious bibliography to sift through
later.
The authors
argue that since adolescence is a time for significant brain development as
well as engagement in psychosocial development (peer group dynamics, sensation
seeking, anhedonia, etc.), that this population is at risk for both a
“psychotic episode and substance abuse disorders in predisposed people” (emphasis mine).
Certainly, the authors would be
remiss not to mention the neural pruning theory of schizophrenia. Indeed they
do, and follow through noting how excessive pruning of neurons in the
prefrontal cortex and the parahippocampal cortex could be responsible for
decreased Dopamine function in the PFC. This, in turn, would lead to over
activity of Dopamine in the mesolimbic system, because of the inhibitory
feedback. That process, in turn, could be responsible for the positive symptoms
of Schizophrenia.
Overall, I was more than pleased to
come across this review of the literature concerning schizophrenia and
substance abuse in adolescents. While the findings presented were not new, nor
did they deviate much (if at all) from the findings presented in previous
research (cf. Carlson’s work referenced below), they nonetheless provide ample
food for thought and as well as a thorough and helpful bibliography.
References
Carlson, N. R. (2010). Physiology of
behavior. Boston, MA: Pearson.
van Nimwegen, L., de Haan, L. L., van Breveren, N. N., van den Brink,
W. W., &
Linszen, D. D. (2005). Adolescence,
schizophrenia and drug abuse: A window
of vulnerability. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 111(s427), 35-42. doi:
10.1111/j.1600-0447.2005.00543.x
By +Phillip J. Kuna
For John G. Kuna, Psy.D. and Associates Counseling
Friday, June 6, 2014
The Central Nervous System: Correlates of Dreams and Waking Hallucinations
In
a previous entry, I explored the connection between the visual system and
visual hallucinations reported by individuals with schizophrenia. Since dreams
can be understood as the nervous system’s processing of endogenous information,
I was interested to understand and explore the correlation between dreams and
hallucinations as they are processed by the nervous system.
Research revealed a fruitful article
by Mahowald, Woods, and
Schenck titled, “Sleeping Dreams, Waking Hallucinations, and the Central
Nervous System.” The authors note that the study concerns the
critical evaluation of “the
similarities and differences between dreams and hallucinations, with particular
reference to the role of the central nervous system in each and with
consideration of their patho-physiologic implications.” More of a review of the
literature than an empirical study, the article had 6
major headings: 1) dream mechanisms, 2) hallucination mechanisms, 3) dreaming
and hallucinations: state disassociation models, 4) hallucinations (spontaneous
and induced) in the non-psychiatric population, 5) dreams and hallucinations as
a manifestation of consciousness, 6) hallucinations in neurological disorders. For the astute reader, a copious and valuable
four pages of references follows the article.
The first section was standard
enough. Their presentation of hallucinatory mechanisms stressed a view of
endogenous brain activity being released when the individual is dissociated
from stimuli: for instance, West’s theory argues that we are always in a dream state;
we just are not attending to it because we are constantly stimulated—we can’t
see the stars during the day, though they are still there.
Section 4, while interesting, wasn’t
my main interest in the article, as it presented topics such: fasting and sleep
deprivation induced hallucinations (especially in religious/mystics), and drug
induced hallucinations. Skipping ahead, the final section (6) provided more
substance to several related areas, including: hallucinations in Parkinson’s
and Alzheimer’s disease, phantom limb syndrome, and Charles Bonnet Syndrome.
Finally,
the fifth section (dreams
and hallucinations as a manifestation of consciousness) had interesting
correlates to schizophrenic hallucinations. We know that the brain is active
during both REM and non REM sleep. Further, we can define consciousness as the
brains awareness of all available data presented to it. While awake, this
information is our environment, external stimuli. While asleep, however, this
stimulus is internally generated. Further, we know from neuroimaging that
during REM sleep there is a decrease in PVC (primary visual cortex) and Frontal
Association activity. From this information, the researchers hypothesize that “the
extrastriate cortices and paralimbic areas may be operating as a closed system,
functionally disconnected from the primary visual and the frontal regions
responsible for the integration of visual information.”
Further evidence for this hypothesis
that consciousness is maintained by the brain’s spatial and temporal mapping
that integrates multiple brain areas can be seen in the fact that both during
REM and the wake state there is a 40 Hz oscillatory rhythm throughout the
cortex. Such a rhythmic oscillation may provide a continuous “neuronal humming”
whereby internal or external irregularities would be conspicuous. What is most
interesting is that this rhythm is reset during the wake state by sensory
stimuli…but it is not reset during REM sleep.
The theory, then, is that some
deviation of either the spatial or temporal regularity of this rhythm may be at
the root of some hallucinations—specifically those experienced by individuals
with schizophrenia. Much of the literature uncovered, however, focused squarely
on the differences between dreams and hallucinations. The convergence of these
themes proved fertile, and we can most certainly anticipate further research
involving this intersection. More so as our neurobiological techniques and
understanding increases. For instance, it was only 40 years ago that the REM phasic event intrusion hypothesis was offered as an explanation for waking
hallucinations in schizophrenia, but this theory was never verified because the
prevailing assumption at the time was that dreaming was confined to REM sleep
only!
References
Mahowald, M. W., Woods, S. R., &
Schenck, C. H. (1998). Sleeping dreams, waking
hallucinations,
and the central nervous system. Dreaming, 8(2), 89-102.
doi:10.1023/B:DREM.0000005899.59224.17
by +Phillip J. Kuna
for John G. Kuna, Psy.D. and Associates
Monday, June 2, 2014
Is Psychology a Science? (Part IV, Conclusion)
Bernard Lonergan |
Method, then, is defined as “a normative pattern of recurrent and related operations yielding cumulative and progressive results” (Lonergan, 1972, p. 4). Here, cumulative results entail a sustained succession of discoveries and progress results indicate synthesis of each new insight that builds upon previously validated insights. Yet transcendental method is more than a mere prescription, a set of rules to follow. Increasing a set of regulations associated with a methodology does not necessarily increase cumulative and progressive results. What is needed, Lonergan argues, is a “prior, normative pattern of operations from which rules may be derived” (Lonergan, 1972, p. 6). Lonergan’s cognitional structure and intentionality analysis provide such an a priori structure with which to inform a methodology.
The implications for such a methodology are nothing short of staggering. If correct, Lonergan’s transcendental method provides the basis for integrating first person data with third person data into a unified theory. As Lonergan explains,
Transcendental method offers a key to unified science…in harmony with all development is the human mind itself which effects the developments. In unity with all fields, however disparate, is again the human mind, which operates in all fields and in radically the same fashion in each (Lonergan, 1972, p. 24).
The process of heightening one’s conscious intentionality, directing one’s awareness to one’s own conscious and cognitional operations is what Lonergan terms self-appropriation. Indeed, the first four chapters of Lonergan’s Insight are nothing short of exercises in self-appropriation. Guiding the reader though a series of thought experiments, the beginning of Insight is meant to allow the reader to reach that eureka moment, and to form an awareness of what happens within themselves during such cognitional procedures. Such self-appropriation is the basis for transcendental method, and is indeed the only way in which to assure accurate first person data as well as a secure methodological foundation:
The derivation of the categories is a matter of the human…subject effecting self-appropriation and employing this heightened consciousness both as a basis for methodological control…as well as an a priori whence he can understand other men [women], their social relations, their history, their religion, their rituals, their destiny (Lonergan, 1972, p. 292).
Further, self-appropriation necessarily implies the employment of Lonergan’s transcendental precepts that correspond to the above cognitional operations: be attentive, be intelligent, be reasonable, and be responsible. Providing an experiential, first person data for these cognitional structures not only enables the duplication and reiteration of these structures, but again, also provides an invariant and structured methodology:
Despite the doubts and denials of positivists and behaviorists, no one, unless some of his [or her] organs are deficient is going to say that never in his life did he have the experience of seeing…of imagining or perceiving, of feeling or moving; or that if he appeared to have such experience, still it was mere appearance, since all of his lifelong he has gone about like a somnambulist without any awareness of his own activities (Lonergan, 1972, p. 16-17).
Finally, Lonergan’s method is trans-cultural. He argues that the rational self-consciousness that can be derived from intentionality analysis is not only normative but also innate to each individual regardless of their cultural milieu. That is, these cognitional features are present in each person, and are the stabilizing feature throughout even, say, a differentiation from a classicist perspective to an empirical one (Lonergan, 1967). The classicist views culture as perennial, absolute, whereas the empiricist is able to adapt to the changing tide of human living, while nonetheless retaining truth (Lonergan, 1972, p. 333). Such a cross cultural methodology would surely be of great interest to many psychologists.
Implications
One may contend that all this philosophy is well and good, but how would one proceed to utilize transcendental method in concrete or therapeutic situations. Brannick (2006) offers a unique voice to the contribution. His unpublished Master’s thesis wove together strands of Lonergan’s thought with emergent probability theory. He concluded by presenting the Rorschach Inkblot Method (RIM) as a possible psychometric instrument with which to empirically validate Lonergan’s claim to unification of the objective and subjective dimensions of human conscious operations. Theoretically, Brannick’s argument is sound. Yet, as he notes in his conclusion, the restructuring of the RIM needed to adapt it to Lonergan’s scheme has yet to be undertaken. I heartily second Brannick’s recommendation for further work on this front.
Further applications of transcendental method are nearly limitless. For instance, one could see how social psychologists would be particularly interested in such a methodology. Answers to questions as how does one conduct a social survey on current topics such as race relations, abortion, or the legal status of gay marriage without being influenced by one’s personal values are neatly answered in Lonergan’s system. Clearly, value-free systems are illusory—either by those conducting the survey or by those surveyed. And while the study of values may properly belong to ethicists, one cannot realistically divorce value-laden systems from human behavior. In that vein, a more appropriate, more Lonerganian approach would be an explicit recognition and divulgence of one’s values. Such values would indicate one’s approach to the survey, and would also dictate why certain questions are raised and not others. Through self-appropriation, values become explicit, enabling a secure and unambiguous foundation for experimentation.
Conclusion
Having situated the topic within the framework of both the historical and emerging paradigms of psychology, we preceded to provide an over-view of the general nature of scientific inquiry. Such an explication was necessary, not only to again situate the discussion of psychology within the other sciences, but more importantly to provide a heuristic basis to the way in which I argued that psychology should view and subsequently proceed as a scientific discipline. The subsequent discussion on the nature and extent of objective-subjective divide within psychology provided concrete instances, which I later implied how Lonergan’s transcendental method would be applicable to such instances. Finally, Lonergan’s transcendental method based both from his cognitional theory and his theory of conscious intentionality was presented as a viable alternative to the pluralistic epistemological accounts now operating in mainstream psychology.
Alarcon (1997) has argued that a unifying paradigm for psychology should be based on 1) philosophical anthropology, 2) the domains within which psychology ought to operate and 3) methodological avenues. Indeed, by grounding objectivity within one’s own subjectivity and rational self-consciousness, Lonergan’s method provides a plausible, reliable and indeed first person empirical alternative to the varied methodological approaches to the study of psychology. As Meynell (1994) has noted,
According to one extreme view of the matter, a true science of humanity would reduce the explanation of human behavior to natural scientific laws. At the other extreme, it is protested that one needs for the human sciences a kind of ‘divinization’, ‘empathy’ or whatever, which is wholly distinct from any procedure to be employed by the natural scientist. Lonergan’s position on the matter at once mediates between these two extremes, and is perfectly consistent within itself. What is particular to the human sciences, in his view, is that the object as well as the subject of inquiry is to be assumed to be more or less intelligent, reasonable and so on, and its behavior to be explained accordingly…in the natural as in the human sciences, one has intelligently and creatively to hypothesize; but in the human as in the natural sciences, one has reasonably to judge one’s hypotheses to be probably true or false according to their corroboration or falsification by relevant observable data (p. 121-122).
I offer one final anecdote in conclusion. Max Planck, the scientist responsible for the revolutionary and fundamental discoveries regarding quantum theory, put forth this question in his autobiography: how is it that a new scientific paradigm becomes accepted within the larger community? Is it the lucidity of the observations? Perhaps it is the exactness of measurements? Or yet still, it may be decisiveness of the experimental results? No, in fact none of these are the cause. The real reason for the advancement of a new scientific revolution, Plank says, is when the present generation of professors is retired (Planck, 1949, p. 33-34). In other words, in the context of paradigmatic shifts, both the social and the hard sciences share the common ground of a rethinking of the basic axioms and postulates inherent to their study—a transformation of the object of their study. In the social sciences, however, and particularly within psychology, the human person is the object of study. What I urge is needed, then, is nothing short of the radical transformation of the human person—who is at once both the subject and object of scientific investigation. Lonergan’s self-appropriation of interiority provides an empirically, self-verified methodology that bridges the subjective—objective dichotomy. As Lonergan puts it, “authentic objectivity is the fruit of authentic subjectivity.” (Lonergan, 1972, p. 292).
By Phillip J. Kuna
For John G. Kuna, Psy.D. and Associates
References
Alarcón R. (1997). La sÃntesis experimental del comportamiento y la unificación de la psicologÃa. Revista Latinoamericana de PsicologÃa, 29 (3), 415-433
Beveridge, A. Time to abandon the subjective—objective divide? The Psychiatrist (2002)
26: 101-103 doi: 10.1192/pb.26.3.101
Bühler, K. (1927). Die Krise der Psychologie. Jena: Verlag von Gustav Fischer.
Brannick, K. J. (2006). Norms of the Mind: Applying Lonergan’s Analysis of Human consciousness to the epistemological crisis in psychological theory and clinical
practice (Master’s thesis). Available from ProQuest Dissertations and Theses
database (Accession No.: 2006-99002-250).
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Cohen, J. (1994). The earth is round (p< .05). American Psychologist, 49(12), 997-1003. Doi:10.1037/0003-066X.49.12.997
Crysdale, C. ed. (1994). Lonergan and Feminism. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
De Feijoo. (2011). La crisis de la subjetividad: Despuntar de las psicologÃas
fenomenológicas. Psicologia em Estudo, 16(3), 409-417.
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown, & Co.
Driver-Linn, E. ( 2003). Where is psychology going? Structural fault lines revealed by psychologists' use of Kuhn. American Psychologist, 58, 269– 278.
Doran, R. (1977). Subject and psyche: Ricoeur, Jung, and the search for foundations. Washington, DC: University Press of America.
Gardner, H. ( 2005). Scientific psychology: Should we bury it or praise it? In R. J.Sternberg (Ed.) , Unity in psychology: Possibility or pipedream? (pp. 77– 90).
Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Goertzen, J. R. (2008). On the possibility of unification: The reality and nature of
the crisis in psychology. Theory & Psychology, 18(6), 829-852. doi:10.1177/0959354308097260
Griffin, D. R. (1991). What is consciousness and why is it so problematic? In K. R. Kao
(Ed.), Cultivating consciousness: Enhancing human potential, wellness, and healing (pp. 51–70). Westport, CT: Praeger.
Grünbaum, A. (1979). Is Freudian psychoanalytic theory pseudo-scientific by Karl
Popper's criterion of demarcation? Psychoanalytic Psychology, 25(4), 574-589. doi:10.1037/a0013540
Grünbaum, A. (2012). Epistemological liabilities of the psychoanalytic method of free association, In M. Holowchak (Ed.), Radical claims in Freudian psychoanalysis: Point/Counterpoint (pp. 167-172). Lanham, MD US: Jason Aronson.
Hay, D. (2007). Something there: The biology of the human spirit. Philadelphia, PA:
Templeton Foundation Press.
Helminiak, D. A. (2013). More Than Awareness: Bernard Lonergan's Multi-Faceted
Account of Consciousness. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology.
Advance online publication. doi: 10.1037/a0031682
Heisenberg, W. (1958). The Physicist's Conception of Nature. London: Hutchinson.
Horstein, Gale. The Return of the Repressed. Psychology’s Problematic Relations with Psychoanalysis 1909-1960.
Husserl, E. (1977). Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. The Hague:
Martinus Nihjoff Publishers.
Kantor, J. R. (1977). Evolution and revolution in the philosophy of science. Revista
Husserl, E. (1977). Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. The Hague:
Martinus Nihjoff Publishers.
Kantor, J. R. (1977). Evolution and revolution in the philosophy of science. Revista
Mexicana de Análisis de la Conducta, 3(1), 7-16.
Kantor, J. R. (1979). Psychology: Science or nonscience? The Psychological Record,
29(2), 155-163.
Kline, P. (1989). Objective tests of Freud's theories. In A. M. Colman, J. Beaumont
(Eds.), Psychology survey, 7 (pp. 127-145). Oxford Florence, England: British Psychological Society.
Koch, S. (1971). Reflections on the state of psychology. Social Research, 38, 669–709.
Koch, S. (1981). The nature and limits of psychological knowledge: Lessons of a century
qua“science.” American Psychologist, 36, 257–269.
Kuhn, T. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: The University of
Chicago Press.
Lacey, H. (1999). Is science value free? Values and scientific understanding. London,
UK: Routledge.
Lonergan, B. J. F. (1967). “Cognitional Structure” in F. E. Crowe (Ed.). Collection:
Papers by Bernard Lonergan (221-239). New York, NY: Herder and Herder.
Lonergan, B. J. F. (1972). Method in theology. New York, NY: Herder and Herder.
Lonergan. B. J. F. (1973). Philosophy of God and Theology: The Relationship between Philosophy of God and the functional Specialty, Systematics. London: Darton
Longman and Todd.
Lonergan, B. J. F. (1974). “An Interview with Fr. Bernard Lonergan, SJ.” In A Second Collection. Philadelphia, PA: The Westminster Press.
Lonergan, B. J. F. (1992). Insight: A study of human understanding. Collected works of
Bernard Lonergan (Vol. 3). Toronto, Canada: Toronto University Press. (Original
work published 1957)
Lonergan, B. J. F. (2002). The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ,
Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan (Vol. 7). (Michael Shields, Trans).
Toronto: University of Toronto Press. (Original work published in 1956)
McShane, P. (1996). Economics for Everyone. Edmonton: Commonwealth Press.
Melchin, K. (1987). History, Ethics and Emergent Probability: Ethics, Society and
History in the Work of Bernard Lonergan. Lanham, MD.: University Press of America.
Meynell, H. (1994). Lonergan's Cognitional Theory and Method in Psychology. Theory Psychology, 4: 105 DOI: 10.1177/0959354394041005
Planck, M. (1949). Scientific Autobiography and Other Papers, trans. F. Gaynor. New
York: Philosophical Library.
Polkinghorne, D. (1982). What makes research humanistic? Journal of Humanistic
Psychology, 22(3), 47-54. doi: 10.1177/0022167882223007
Popper, K. (1935). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York, NY: Science Editions,
Inc.
Rogers, C. (1961). On Becoming a Person. New York, NY: Houghton Mifflin Company.
Rogers, C. (1965). Client Centered Therapy. New York, NY: Houghton Mifflin Company.
Rychlak, J. F. ( 2005). Unification in theory and method: Possibilities and
impossibilities. In R.J. Sternberg (Ed.), Unity in psychology: Possibility or pipedream? (pp. 145– 158). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Searle, J. R. (1997). The mystery of consciousness. New York, NY: The New York Review
of Books.
Staats, A.W. (1983). Psychology’s crisis of disunity: Philosophy and method for a unified science. New York: Praeger Publishers.
Staats, A. W. (1999). Unifying psychology requires new infrastructure, theory, method,
and a research agenda. Review of General Psychology, 3(1), 3-13. 10.1037/1089-2680.3.1.3
Staats, A. W. (1998). Unifying psychology: A scientific or non-scientific theory task?
Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 18(1), 70-79. 10.1037/h0091317
Stam, H. J. (2004). Unifying Psychology: Epistemological Act or Disciplinary
Maneuver? Journal Of Clinical Psychology, 60(12), 1259-1262. doi:10.1002/jclp.20069
Tharp, R. G. (2007). A perspective on unifying culture and psychology: Some
philosophical and scientific issues. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, Vol 27-28(2-1), 213-233. doi: 10.1037/h0091294
Thorndike, E. (1932), The Fundamentals of Learning. New York, NY: Bureau of
Publications, Teacher’s College, Columbia University.
Yanchar, S.C. (1997). Fragmentation in focus: History, integration, and the project of
evaluation. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 17, 150-171.
Zavershneva, E. (2012). Investigating L.S. Vygotsky’s Manuscript “The Historical
Meaning of the Crisis in Psychology.” Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 50(4), 42-63. doi: 10.2753/RPO1061-0405500402
Friday, May 30, 2014
Is Psychology a Science? (Part III)
contributions. By his own admission, his academic career was carried out "under impossible conditions," within a system that was "hopelessly antiquated" (Lonergan, 1973, p. 15). It was a system that, in neglecting the need for specialization in modernity, relied too heavily on the outdated concept of the homo universale while simultaneously operating within both an insufficient philosophy and a classicist notion of culture (Lonergan, 1974, pp. 209-210)
The
archaic and perennial philosophy to which Lonergan revolted was the
metaphysical system developed by St. Thomas Aquinas, who in turn relied heavily
on Aristotle. It was a metaphysical system based on the archaic notion of a
faculty psychology. Faculty psychology suggests that the mind consists of
different powers, or faculties: the intellect, the will, and the emotions—all the
while presupposing a Cartesian mind-body dualism. Indeed, faculty psychology’s
grip was so strong that it remained the prevailing learning theory until the early 20th century when Edward Thorndike, the
student of William James, published groundbreaking studies on learning in
animals and humans (Thorndike,
1932). Clearly, such
a faculty psychology would not be sufficient to address the emerging concerns
of the 20th century.
Lonergan’s
project, then, was an attempt to take into account the Enlightenment’s turn to
the subject while at the same time constructing a methodology that would avoid
the Kantian epidemic of collapsing in on itself. Thus, Lonergan asserts that
while metaphysics may still be first in itself, it is no longer the foundation
that it once was. Rather, he takes cognitional operations and intentionality analysis,
as his starting point (intentionality analysis refers here to the philosophy of
Lonergan’s Transcendental Method, of which his cognitional theory forms the
basis). It has as its basis the
following pre-suppositions: 1) humans have an unrestricted, unlimited, detached
and disinterested desire to know (as is evidenced in the constant questioning,
that any parent of a toddler is familiar with), 2) a normative and fixed
pattern of recurring mental and cognitional operations involved in the process
of inquiry and investigation, and 3) immanent norms of intelligence, reasonableness
and responsibility that guide the cognitive dimension of human consciousness (Lonergan,
1992).
What
Lonergan provides then, is a cognitional theory that informs a theory of
consciousness, which in turn informs a metaphysics and an ethics. The
decisiveness of Lonergan’s theory can be seen in sharp distinction to the many
conflicting and often overwhelming theories of consciousness currently in
vogue. Even a brief survey of the psychological literature on consciousness
studies reveals multifaceted methodologies often based on inaccurate or
incomplete foundations. Searle (1997), for instance, appeals to perceptual
models to describe the imperceptibleness of consciousness. Others (Dennett,
1991; Griffin, 1991; Hay, 2007) maintain that mental images and representations
are necessary to explain the invisibleness of consciousness. Finally, still
others (Chalmers, 1996) argue that while attempts to explain the invisible are
all well and good, but what is physical is ultimately real. The irony of course
is that even those in the hard sciences—say, particle physics for
instance—understand that the particles they are discussing are often times
simply constructs of human intelligence. Such constructs, while not ultimately
tangible, are ways to explain what must indeed be so if they are to offer an
explanation of what has actually been observed. In other words, the future of
the science of psychology may be contingent upon the integration of both the
objective and subjective components inherent in human cognition.
While
Lonergan’s method has received great attention in the fields of philosophy,
theology, ethics (Melchin, 1987), feminist studies (Crysdale, 1994) and even
economics (McShane, 1996), there is a notable lack of application of his method
in the field of psychology. Proceeding now to summarize Lonergan’s account of
the unfolding of human consciousness, the explication and defense of each
unique and distinct philosophical position will be clearly untenable. I refer the
curious to his original works.
Non-reflexive
Consciousness
Lonergan
distinguishes between what he terms reflexive consciousness and non-reflexive consciousness. Generally,
consciousness is defined here as an “interior experience, of oneself and one’s
acts, where experience is taken in the strict sense of the word” (Lonergan,
2002, p. 157). It is the strict sense insofar as it differs from an undefined
knowledge. It is experiential insofar as it is a direct awareness of data,
which initiates a process of intellectual inquiry to understand what has been
experienced and to pronounce judgment on its reality.
Non-Reflexive consciousness, then,
is conscious awareness of awareness. Such a cognitional act does not imply an
object. Rather, it is an experiential awareness of one’s own subjectivity. Again,
such awareness is not found by naval-gazing introspection. Introspection would
only reveal the subject as object. To discern the subject as subject one has
merely to increase one’s level of activity. “If one sleeps and dreams, one
becomes present to oneself as the frightened dreamer. If one wakes, one becomes
present to oneself, not as moved but as moving.” (Lonergan, 1967, p. 227)
Inasmuch as it is an experience of
one’s acts, Lonergan argues that while one performs their daily tasks of living
they are aware, not only of the sensations and data of experience, but also
aware of the acts themselves. For example, right now as I hear my dog bark, I
can recognize not only the sounds, but I am also able to attend to the fact
that I am hearing. Again, I can decide that my dog needs to be taken outside.
In this instance, I am aware not only of the decision to take him out, but also
of my own cognitional state of deciding and finally of myself as deciding
(Lonergan, 1967, pp. 175-176).
A
further clarification rests on Lonergan’s distinction between consciousness and
reflexive knowledge. Consciousness is not to be confused with reflexive
knowledge. Consciousness, in Lonergan’s terms, comes prior to reflexive
self-knowledge, and as such, is the subject’s experience of oneself as subject.
Reflexive self-knowledge, on the other hand, completes the direct awareness of
consciousness by forming and verifying concepts through the subject’s
self-experience (Lonergan, 1967, pp. 177-178).
A
comparative analysis should yield further clarification. Lonergan demarcates
his own line of thought from the many prevailing opinions that consider
consciousness to be some sort of introspection, or positions that describes or
implies that conscious awareness involves some sort of inward looking.[1]
Termed Conscientia-perceptio[2] by
Lonergan, this view supposes that consciousness is the same process as direct
knowing. Yet such analogies fail here, for in non-reflexive consciousness, there
is no subject-object relationship governing the cognitive processes. Rather, it
is simply objectless awareness, with no objectified aspect of self. That is to
say, my knowledge of my dog is not equivalent to the way in which I am aware of
myself. In both cases there is knowledge of an object. Notable is that in the
second case that subject knows oneself as an object. The problem with conscientia-perceptio, Lonergan argues,
is that a cognitive act does not constitute any effect in its object. That is,
if consciousness is direct self-knowledge, then it would have no constitutive
effect on the self, thereby reducing the subject’s psychological unity to
beyond the object in one’s range of knowledge. This distinction between non-reflexive
and reflexive consciousness is crucial for Lonergan, for it is “the difference
between conscious and unconscious acts” (Lonergan, 1992, p. 322). That is, it
is from the subjective and conscious awareness (non-reflecting consciousness)
from which the objectification of cognitional acts of reflecting consciousness
emerge. The following section describes Lonergan’s account of reflexive consciousness—the
intentional acts of human consciousness that enable us to grasp the inherent
intelligibility of both internal and external stimuli.
Reflexive
Consciousness and Intentionality Analysis
For
Lonergan, the objectification of subjective stimuli, both external and
internal, occurs as one’s reflexive consciousness unfolds through four distinct
levels. Levels here should be understood metaphorically. Spatial and temporal
analogies of human conscious tend to fail since they imply an ocular component
to consciousness. Further, unlike the direct awareness of self-provided by
non-reflexive consciousness, reflexive consciousness always intends an object
(Lonergan, 1967).
The
acts of reflexive consciousness that intends both internal and external
objects, Lonergan argues, are governed by four distinct levels of
intentionality. The four levels of intentionality—conscious awareness (attention),
intelligent understanding (intelligence), reasonable judgment (reasonableness),
and responsible decision (responsibility)—are proposed to be the normative and
recurrent pattern of human cognition. That is, in conjunction with the ongoing
and non-objectified self-awareness of non-reflexive consciousness, cognitive
operations experienced in the form of questioning, provide an orientation
toward objectification of an attended to stimuli—again, whether external or
internal.
The
first level of conscious intentionality, attending to the stimulus at hand,
implies more than mere looking. In Lonergan’s system, conscious awareness and
attention imply the “detached, disinterested desire to know” (Lonergan, 1992,
p. 10). It implies a thrust of wonder, of curiosity, of marvel. Such is the
wonder Aristotle spoke of, citing it as the beginning of all philosophy and
scientific knowledge. Such is the wonder of the young child, who with innocent and
unwavering curiosity interrogates his parents with questions ad infinitum.[3]
Lonergan
describes the second level of conscious intentionality, intelligent
understanding, in this way: “an intellectual level on which we inquire, come to
understand, express what we have understood, and work out the presuppositions
and implications of our position” (Lonergan, 1992, p. 9). The understanding and
insights produced by intelligently probing the data received through conscious
awareness opens up then further questions that can only be answered by
advancement to the third level of reasonable judgment.
Reasonable
judgment answers to the question, “Is it so? Is it not so? Is it?” In
Lonerganian terms: the insights, hypotheses, and theories propounded in the
second level of conscious intentionality, intelligent understanding, are put to
the strict demands of rational judgment. As Lonergan (1992) explains, the third
level contains
The effective
operation of a single law of utmost generality, the law of sufficient reason is
where the sufficient reason is the unconditioned. It emerges as a demand for
the unconditioned and the refusal to assent unreservedly on any lesser ground.
It advances to a grasp of the unconditioned. It terminates in the rational
compulsion by which grasp of the unconditioned commands assent (p. 346).
Here, the unconditioned simply
means that all pertinent questions have been answered. If a person comes home
after a long day at work, see smoke in the air and water on the floor, can he
assume there was a fire? Have all pertinent questions been answered? According
to Lonergan, he has not yet answered all pertinent questions, and therefore
cannot be said to have grasped the virtually unconditioned. All one say in the
above scenario is that there is smoke in the air and water on the floor, and
something has happened.
Finally,
Lonergan’s fourth level of conscious intentionality, responsible decision,
entails the raising and answering of questions that imply a reasonable and
responsible course of action. Similar to personal agency, such an concept of
responsible decision implies that human beings can freely choose a course of
action that is either consistent or inconsistent to what has been determined to
be reasonable understanding (second level) of the attended (first level) to
data (Lonergan, 1972).
Attempts
to deny Lonergan’s cognitional structure and theory of conscious intentionality
would imply that the commentator has not attended to the data, is
unintelligent, unreasonable, or sound asleep. That is, any attempts to refute
Lonergan’s claims would necessarily involve the operations outlined above,
namely—attending to the data presented, grasping the intelligibility of the
theory, and making a reasonable judgment of its veracity (Lonergan, 1972, p.
17).
Up to this point, we have outlined
in broad strokes the basis for Lonergan’s methodology.
Thus far, we have
looked to the success of the natural sciences to gather a preliminary
understanding of methodology. We have taken a detour behind the techniques of
the natural sciences to the fundamentals of the cognitional operations of the
human mind. From those basic processes of the human mind, a transcendental
method[4]
can be discerned—basic patterns and operations that are employed, cross
culturally, in every cognitional enterprise. From there, the formulation of
such a transcendental method can be accurately applied to special methodologies
appropriate for particular fields of study (Lonergan, 1972, p. 4). As Lonergan
(1972) notes,
However true it is
that one attends, understands, judges, decides differently in the natural
sciences, in the human sciences, as in theology, still the difference in no way
imply or suggest a transition from attention to inattention, from intelligence
to stupidity, from reasonableness to silliness, from responsibility to
irresponsibility (p. 23).
Part IV of this
post will conclude by outlining an application of Lonergan’s method to the
science of psychology.
By Phillip Kuna
For John G. Kuna, Psy.D. and
Associates Counseling
[1] A select few of
psychology’s prevailing theories of consciousness that employ such perceptual
models were covered earlier, if but briefly.
[2] Lonergan, 2002, p. 181.
The phrase can be loosely translated from the Latin as “perceptive
consciousness”.
[3] For more on this
orientation of wonder, and its subsequent decline with age, see Lonergan
(2012), chapters 6 and 7.
[4] The method is
transcendental because it goes beyond (transcends) itself by the raising of
further questions.
Labels:
cognition,
cognitive,
consciousness,
epistemology,
method,
methodology,
psychology,
science
Location:
Scranton, PA, USA
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)